Antonio Sennis (ed.), Cathars in Question, (Heresy and
Inquisition in the Middle Ages vol.4, York Medieval Press 2016), vii, 332pp.
Reviewed by Elaine Graham-Leigh (www.redpuffin.co.uk)
The question of whether or not Western Europe from the
mid-twelfth century onwards saw the development of organised dualist heresy is
a contentious one. In R I Moore’s words, it has ‘proved not to be susceptible
of resolution by the ordinary procedures of historical method alone.’ (p.273)
This collection of essays records an attempt to shed some light on the issue,
at the Catharism conference at University College London in 2013, subtitled
‘Balkan Heresy or Construct of a Persecuting Society?’
The subtitle is a fair summary of the battle lines on the
Cathar question. In what might be termed the traditionalist corner is the view
that Catharism, a dualist heresy departing from orthodox Christianity in
believing in two Gods, the evil god of this world and the good god of heaven,
arrived in western Europe from the Bogomils in Bulgaria and the Balkans in
around 1140. It took root in Italy, the Rhineland and southern France, with
sects forming their own ecclesiastical hierarchies, with bishops, deacons and
dioceses, functioning as something akin to an alternative Church, until they
were destroyed by the Inquisition.
In the sceptic corner, Catharism as an ‘ism’ is the creation
first of hierarchically-minded inquisitors and second of similarly
bureaucratically-biased historians. There is no evidence for organised dualism
anywhere in western Europe in the twelfth century. The evidence for its
existence by the mid-thirteenth century in Italy is better, but the
significance of this evidence for the wider understanding of heresy is
debatable. In Languedoc in particular, the heretics simply represented a local
version of Christian spirituality, and only started to organise themselves (or
to claim organisational structures) under attack by Inquisition and the
Albigensian Crusade from the early thirteenth century. Even late in the
thirteenth century, heresy here was as much about dissent from the Church as it
was about doctrinal difference. So far from being an organised alternative
Church, heretics in Languedoc did not call themselves Cathars and were not
referred to as such by the inquisitors. When they were called anything beyond
‘followers of the heretical depravity’, they were termed simply ‘good men’ or
‘good women’.
As Moore points out in his essay here, the two sides in this
debate have ‘a surprising degree of agreement on such facts as are capable of
being established.’ (p.257) The differences are in how these facts should be
interpreted. On one level, this concerns our understanding of the fragmentary
evidence for twelfth-century dualism, such as the contentious record of the
Cathar Council of Saint-Félix. This was supposedly a meeting of organised
dualists held in Languedoc in 1167, presided over by a certain Niquinta,
identified as Nicetas, a Byzantine Greek and representative of the Bogomils.
According to the surviving account, the Council consecrated three Cathar
bishops and organised the boundaries of their dioceses, and so, if it can be
relied upon, it is important evidence for organised dualism. The account is not,
however, without its problems.
The account of the Council is contained in a charter dated
1232, which survives only in a copy in a seventeenth-century history of the
Dukes of Narbonne by Guillaume Besse. Historians of medieval Languedoc are
particularly reliant on seventeenth-century copies since many of the original
charters were destroyed in the French Revolution. Many of these copies are
reasonably reliable, beyond the odd copying error that could happen to anyone,
but the Saint-Félix account has long been controversial, to the extent that a
colloque was held in 2000 to consider its authenticity or otherwise. The
colloque concluded that the document was unlikely to be a seventeenth-century
forgery, although Monique Zerner, the organiser, remains sceptical as a result
of her discovery of what look like earlier attempts by Besse at forging it.
This does not preclude the possibility of it being a thirteenth-century
forgery. It is certainly true that there are issues with the document which
make its acceptance as an unimpeachable source a little tricky. One of the
participants in the framing 1232 charter, for example, is named as Peire Isarn,
called a bishop of the heretics in an Inquisition record from 1223. This Peire
Isarn, however, was burnt for heresy in 1226. Bernard Hamilton, defending the
document, argues that it is simply wrongly dated, with a copying error giving
1232 for its real date of 1223, but this smacks a little of special pleading.
While this would be a simple transposition error in Arabic numerals, it is not
such an obvious mistake when working in Roman. (p.141)
For the traditionalists, the Cathar Council shows how the
heretics were imitating Church hierarchy and structure even in the twelfth
century; for the sceptics, it is more likely to represent an attempt to claim an
organisation and an antiquity which did not in fact exist. In that sense, it
can be seen as an early example of what the sceptics see as a methodological
error in the traditional approach, in that it creates a picture of heresy in
the twelfth century through the prism of conditions in the thirteenth. If it is
assumed that the clear presence of organised dualists in Italy by about 1250
means that there must also have been such organised dualism in Languedoc in the
twelfth century, then evidence like the description of the Cathar Council of
Saint-Félix becomes both more plausible and the tip of a heretical iceberg,
existing just as it did a century later but only revealed in fragments. If, as
the sceptics do, we take the view that the thirteenth-century evidence should
not be read back on to the twelfth, then the twelfth-century scraps of evidence
take on a different complexion.
It may be a rule that a methodological disagreement among
historians is more likely to be vituperative than a dispute about facts. Moore
comments that the conference’s aim was to reassess Catharism ‘through a debate
in a non-confrontational spirit’ (p.257), but the tone of some of the articles
here suggests that this was not entirely achieved. Here, for example, is
sceptic Mark Pegg on historians who defend Catharism as a reality:
What distinguishes historians who persist in accepting (and defending) the reality of Catharism is…"how little they aim to produce major novelties, conceptual or phenomenal". This blinkered competence, where the achievements of older scholars are solemnly replicated, and all new research is wilfully ignored, consistently misunderstood, or vehemently rejected (and, every so often, a curious mix of all three), encourages either a studious treading of intellectual waters, hoping against hope that the tide is not turning, or a learned backstroke to around 1970, although, depending on the current, it is, more often than not, 1870. (p.21)
Not to be outdone, traditionalist John Arnold comments that
Pegg’s conception of a locally-rooted spirituality represented by the good men
had him sliding towards an Occitan nationalism ‘some of which is staunchly
socialist, but other strands of which have roots in the Vichy regime.’ (p.75)
David D’Avray, meanwhile, sums up Moore’s The War on Heresy in an elegantly
silky put-down:
The key passages occur near the end of the book, by which time it would be easy for a reader to have decided what its central argument was and to miss Moore's conscientious record of evidence that complicates the overall picture, especially since the central thrust of the argument is foreground and the complexities are fitted in smoothly and quite unobtrusively, as in an Economist article. (p.177)
Both sides also at times imply that those on the other are
guilty of incompetence at best, as for example in Peter Biller’s comments on
mistranslations to omit Cathar titles in Moore’s The War on Heresy, (p.303) and
Pegg’s that traditionalists like Caterina Bruschi and John Arnold interpret
Inquisition sources as if oblivious to chronology. (p.36) Antonio Sennis, as
referee, abstains from the more colourful language but does not manage to be
quite even-handed, coming down in favour, for example, of key traditionalist
pieces of evidence like the Saint-Félix document. That the last word is given
to arch-traditionalist Peter Biller may also be a suggestion of in which
direction the editorial sympathies lay.
Such academic bad temper may make the collection
entertaining reading for those of us whose works, mercifully, are not referred
to by either side. There are however differences of real importance here. The
implications of the sceptical view go beyond the question of how evidence from
the thirteenth century can, or cannot, be used to illuminate the twelfth, to
throw into question our entire use of Inquisition records as reliable evidence
for the nature and extent of organised heresy.
The traditional view treats the Inquisition records which
form the bulk of the evidence for heresy as largely truthful accounts of what
was said to the inquisitors. The inquisitors may have been interpreting and
expressing the testimonies in language and concepts familiar to them, but in
essence, they were recording what they found. For the sceptics, on the other
hand, the Inquisition records show what the inquisitors expected to hear from
those they interrogated; expectations which shaped both how they recorded
testimonies and what the heresy suspects told them. This is not say that the
Inquisition records are not useful as historical sources, but they cannot be
treated as one step away from interview transcripts. This understanding of the
nature of the Inquisition records poses distinct challenges for how they can be
used to reconstruct what may have lain behind individual testimonies. It also
calls into question assumptions that the traditional view has made about the
big picture of heresy in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries.
The traditional view of inquisitors as honest recorders of
the heresy they found assumes first that this heresy had an objective existence
outside the prejudices and expectations of the inquisitors. If the Inquisition
had not existed, the heresy would still have been there; and presumably with
greater numbers of believers, since part of the traditional view is usually the
conclusion that the Inquisition was fundamentally successful. The areas on
which the inquisitors came to concentrate, and from which the greatest numbers
of heresy convictions came, can therefore be taken to be those with the
greatest prevalence of objectively-existing heresy. Thus, for example, Malcolm
Lambert comments in his The Cathars about Carcassonne’s revolt against the
Inquisition in the late thirteenth century: ‘Authority stood firm; the evidence
is sufficient to show that the accusations were not generally based on
prejudice and that despite irregularities the old religion still had a residual
hold, even among its high officials and leading citizens.’ (Malcolm Lambert,
The Cathars (Blackwell, Oxford 1998), p.227)
It is indeed true that Carcassonne saw many more heresy
accusations than some other neighbouring towns, like Narbonne, which had
markedly few. The implication of the sceptical view of the Inquisition evidence
however is that this does not indicate that there were simply fewer heretics in
Narbonne than in Carcassonne. It suggests that there were so many accusations
of heresy in Carcassonne because the Inquisition was there, and comparatively
little heresy in Narbonne because here the inquisitors did not have free rein. The
inquisitors were not diligently rooting out heresy which would have been
flourishing without them so much as creating it through repression.
The question of whether and how authorities should deal with
what they perceive to be dangerously deviant thought is a decidedly
contemporary one, and one which is clearly an ethical issue for a number of the
authors here. This is perhaps another reason why the debate has become more
than usually fraught. John Arnold does not see the traditional/sceptic division
as a left/right political issue, speculating that the Anglophone scholars at
least ‘would all see themselves as left-leaning to at least some degree.’
(p.73) Within that, however, he sees the sceptic position as seeing the people
of Languedoc and northern Italy too much as passive victims of repression: ‘to
make ‘heresy’ only the product of orthodox power is to impute to that power an
overwhelming hegemony that is in danger of making the people subjected to it
disappear.’ (p.76) To view them as organised heretics, on the other hand, is to
see them as active agents, capable of fighting back. For her part, Claire
Taylor sees sceptical denial of the religious motivations of heretics as the
key moral problem: ‘This matters at an ethical level, because by being cleverly
iconoclastic and populist in suggesting that those using 'Cathar' have made
2+2=5, Pegg and now Moore have 2+2=3. The missing element is a dissident
religious doctrine, for which historians using a fuller range of sources
believe thousands of people were prepared to suffer extreme persecution and an
agonising death.’ (p.244)
The sceptics’ case also has a political side, although not
perhaps stated as explicitly in this volume. The traditionalist view of
Catharism presents it as an outside-context problem for the Church. Heretics
and their ideas infected parts of medieval Europe from the East, and had to be
dealt with. While it would be hard to find any modern historian actively
supporting the Inquisition, it is notable particularly in traditionalist
accounts how sympathetically the inquisitors are often portrayed. We may not
approve of their methods, but there often seems to be a tacit understanding
that faced with the objective existence of an existential threat in Catharism,
they had to do something. If, however, this foreign, organised dualism had no
real existence independent of attempts to eradicate it, then the question we
are asking becomes why it was necessary to construct unorganised dissent as an
existential threat, and what that leads us to understand about the nature of
medieval power.
A sceptical view of heresy in the twelfth and thirteenth
centuries certainly does not have to deny agency to those persecuted by the
Inquisition, or to see them as passive victims because it does not see them as
Cathars. As Théry-Astruc points out in this volume, all sorts of dissent,
including opposition to the Inquisition, were routinely classified as heresy,
as was opposition to the Albigensian Crusade, even late in the thirteenth
century. (A Toulousan accused of inciting a riot in 1269 by shouting out that
‘we are as oppressed as the Jews of Jew Street’ defended himself with the claim
that his father and brother had fought alongside the crusaders.) There was
plenty of resistance so to classify. By the late thirteenth century,
Carcassonne and Albi were in near-constant rebellion against the Inquisition,
culminating in 1303 when the people of Carcassonne expelled the inquisitors and
broke open the Inquisition prison. Many of the participants in this long-running
resistance were condemned as heretics, but we have no real evidence that they
were members of an organised heretical sect, or that they believed any
unorthodox doctrine. They were simply opposed to the Inquisition, and prepared
to use their agency to rebel against it.
Accounts of heresy in Languedoc and Italy from the twelfth
to the twenty-first century have tended to reify it; to turn it into an ‘ism’
with a defined hierarchy and set of beliefs. Without the edifice that is
Catharism, we are faced with a more nuanced picture of the interplay of
repression and resistance. This is perhaps more challenging than the
comfortable orthodoxy, but it has also the potential to be more rewarding. One
effect of understanding Catharism as a foreign body infecting Languedoc in
particular has been to divide how we see Languedoc from how we view
spirituality and dissent elsewhere in Europe. If other areas were not infected
by Catharism, how could they be usefully comparable? It may well be, however,
that figures like the good men of Languedoc were not unknown elsewhere in
Europe, it was just that in those other parts of Europe, they did not have to
be treated as heretics. The sceptical view opens up the possibility of
considering the reasons for that difference. Our understanding of medieval
Europe would be all the better for it.
Elaine Graham-Leigh
Independent scholar
Elaine Graham-Leigh is the author of The Southern French Nobility and the Albigensian Crusade (Boydell and Brewer, 2005).
Independent scholar
Elaine Graham-Leigh is the author of The Southern French Nobility and the Albigensian Crusade (Boydell and Brewer, 2005).